Skip to main content

Rawls, Violence, and the State

Given the rise of the security state, one critique Rawls' work increasingly faces is that he did not give enough due attention to the problems of war and the violent capacity of the state.

As an example, Paul Kahn in Political Theology charges that “Rawls and his followers never took seriously the violence of the state,” because the threat of “mutual assured destruction never appears within liberal political theory.” Further “the defence policies of the United States are always seen as somehow exceptional—more transitional arrangements than expressions of national identity.” 

(Of secondary interest, Kahn holds that state violence derives less from conflict about political identity and affiliation, and more from the deeper realm of the apparent lawful order wherein“political violence has been and remains a form of sacrifice.” For Kahn the disadvantage of the majority of liberal political theory is that it cannot make that identification for “not reason but decision describes that most characteristic of all political acts: killing and being killed for the state.” The American carceral state is form of sacrifice made for political order.)

In other words, Rawlsian liberals overlook how violence is a salient feature of American foreign policy. 

The charge is used as proxy to indict the ideal of justice as fairness; for if justice relies upon the state for implementation. And if that institution is at its very core is violent and corrupt, then how can any system of justice implement in its name be just?

A compelling conclusion. But is the evidence sound?

For myself, Kahn, as well as other critics of liberalism, fall into the trap of sentimentalism, believing incorrectly at the absence of a particular kind of demonstrated concern for a particular topic indicates its absence altogether. It is the emphasis of empathy while neglecting the merits of sympathy.

While Rawls did shy away from public engagement, this does not mean that he had few political opinions, nor any positions on war or violence in general. 
For Rawl, instances of war were the very items that turned him away from religious belief (although not religious temperament) to political philosophy. 

In his reflective essay "On My Religion," he writes about some of his military experience in the general infantry in the Pacific theater, and his horror at the use of the atomic bombs, the discovery of the concentration camps, and the contingent death of a close friend. Rawls knew war.

Moreover Rawls took an early public stance against the Vietnam War, understanding it as an unjust war. In 1969 Rawls choose to teach a class on the Problems of War because of its timely nature. Issues covered includes ius as bellum and ius in bello, conscientious objections to serving in an unjust war, and civil disobedience. These ideas would find themselves articulated in Political Liberalism.

There is also his 1969 paper “The Justification of Civil Disobedience" which established justified citizens as dissenters in publicly and non-violently disobeying the law, within limits to the fidelity to the law. These are some notable instances which provide philosophical support to the ideas of dissent of the civil rights movement. 

And in 1995 on the Fiftieth anniversary of the Hiroshima atomic bombing, Rawls published a paper condemning the actions, writing that they “were great wrongs.”

I don't think there is evidence for Kahn’s argument. In general he neglects that liberals have often been at the forefront of reforming indiscriminate state violence. Hence why liberal social contact theorists of morality demand that 'might cannot be right,' and instead seek to base political decisions on reason.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Authority and American Autobiographies

Craig Fehrman has a piece up at Vox on the  changing trends in American life-writing. Part way  through Fehrman makes an interesting observation on authority: In the first half of the 19th century only the clergy and criminals published autobiographies.  One group had divine authority to tell their life stories. The other had nothing left to lose. His essay ends by celebrating digital media as enabling a democratization of life-stories with Instagram et al representing a broader shift of authority from the nexus of the state and civic status to the personal realm. One might even think of this near century long turn as a great recommission of private meaning, one in which things of a private nature could be recast as being of public relevance, bringing with it accountability, justification, explanation, and special pleading. These are all the kinds of exchanges that come with the giving and taking of reasons along with the implicit knowledge that one might be found wanting by ones

Caribbean Case Selection

One of my more recent research projects has been tracking factors shaping the development of Caribbean Studies. Below is a  preliminary data visualization of case selection by country. Quantities mark the number of times a county / region has been used as a case study.

Derrida Playing Cricket.

  I will never be the better theorist, but I can rest assured that I am the better batsman.